Did we really have a summer?? |
Academy B & B Graduate Room |
I watched an episode of Lang & O'Leary Exchange on
CBC last night. An item they discussed was the threat of a strike among
elementary school teachers in Ontario. (I use the word discussed
loosely; it was actually a quarrel between the two on their diametrically
opposed views on unions. O'Leary stood by his conviction that unions are evil
and should be banned; Lang defended their efficacy on the basis that there is
no other way to prevent worker exploitation other than a banding together along
with the power to withdraw labour.)
Clearly,
neither of them was likely to change his/her mind. The “righteous mind” is
seldom swayed by reasonable arguments.
Which takes
me to a useful tool for rethinking how we arrive at moral stances and how these
stances—so often set in stone, apparently—do and don't change. The Righteous
Mind: Why Good People are Divided by Politics and Religion by Jonathan
Haidt tackles a very tough but highly relevant subject. I'm barely into it, but
I'm already sensing that I've gone about my attempts at moral suasion (when
they've arisen) in a fruitless and wrong-headed way.
Think of us
as having two parts. One is intuition/emotion (the affective domain, if you
will) and the other is reason (the cognitive domain). Historically, according
too Haidt, reason has been given too much credit as being the birthplace of our
moral positioning. In other words, we've assumed that having been given the facts,
we apply them and arrive at logical, rational positions.
According to
Haidt, current research shows that moral positions are gained in the affective
domain and cognition (reasoning) has the primary task of justifying the
position by rallying whatever favourable evidence can be conjured or found.
Only seldom is change in initial positions observable as a consequence of
reasoned argument.
Here's a
typical Haidt scenario. A researcher gathers 30 students in a room and asks
them to make a judgement on the following situation: a family's pet dog is hit
by a car and killed. In order to avoid being wasteful, they cook and eat the
dog. What do you think of that? Most respondents assert quite strongly that it
is both wrong and revolting. When the logic that a) we eat animals all the
time, b) that the dog is dead and c) will feel no pain nor indignity and d)
that there is no law against eating dogs, the respondents don't typically
change their position, but instead, try to justify it with reasons like, “Well,
it's an indignity to the pet.” Some will simply say, “I don't know why it's
wrong; it just is.”
The
revulsion against eating dog, let alone pet dogs, is deeply engrained in our
affective beings. We cannot be rational about an act like the one portrayed in
the test.
It's not
surprising that some of us are politically conservative for life and others are
equally social-democratic. The underlying orientation is not generally won
through rational analysis of the two positions; most of us can can trace back to the
beginnings of our “leaning” where we're likely to find a parent and/or teachers
who leaned the same way so that our stance politically is all bound up with
emotional attachments and revulsions dating back to early days.
Most men
lean left or right in concert with their fathers, unless they hate them, in
which case they may obstinately demonstrate their feelings by leaning the other
way . . . in defiance.
The quarrels
about the presence or exclusion of gays in churches have by now become classic
in the story of the Christian Church. On the one side—the “liberal” side—a
litany of reasons for treating gays evenhandedly has had virtually no
effect on the “conservative” side's stance that a gay lifestyle cannot be
scripturally supported, is therefore sin and has no place in the communion of
Christians. According to Haidt's view, I would say that this deviation of moral
stances cannot be resolved no matter how many and forcefully the reasons on
either side are trumpeted. The division is embedded in the affective domains,
the centres of emotion and intuition, i.e. the relatively stable moral
predispositions of the people involved.
The quarreling around contentious issues is a clamouring for reasons in
support of an exceedingly stable position.
Accepting
Haidt's contention that “intuition precedes reason” should help us mitigate the
rancorous divisions we live with, both religious and political. At the
political level, governing parties should take initiative in fostering
affective relationships among all legislators; it's through relationship and
relationship alone that good governance might finally become a reality. Imagine
a question period that is amiable and courteous, an opposition working at the
same problems as the government and a government happy for their help because
they have developed the appropriate intuitive and emotional trust of each
other’s intentions.
♫Wouldn't it
be nice♫
Regarding
the quarrel in churches over the inclusion or exclusion of people living a gay
lifestyle, suffice it to say that the end result of the arguing won't lead to
unity if Haidt is right. That's been amply demonstrated already. It hasn't been
that long since gays were given tacit permission to be openly gay. As
time passes, the liberal viewpoint will eventually dominate given that youth
are growing up in an environment of greater tolerance of non-conventional sexual
orientation.
Meanwhile, there
remain two alternatives: church members and congregations can separate ties and
regroup with those who share the same moral stance on the subject, or members
and congregations could agree to disagree on the particular matter and focus on
those things on which they share intuitive and emotional common ground.
That,
too, would be nice.
Meanwhile,
I suggest you don't waste your time with Lang and O'Leary Exchange if
it's enlightenment you're looking for. Intuition precedes reason, remember.